Does China Enjoy Greater Legitimacy Than Any Western State?
I was listening to the radio a little while ago, and heard Martin Jacques talking about China. I listened with renewed concentration. Jacques was formerly editor of Marxism Today,
so he is a man who knows a thing or two about oppressive
pseudo-socialist regimes. Much of what Jacques had to say was
insightful, but one of his claims seemed surprising. Warning his
audience he was about to shock them, Jacques asserted that ‘the Chinese
state enjoys greater legitimacy than any Western state’. This is, by
any standards, a courageous claim to make. Jacques advanced three,
connected, arguments to support it. First, he drew our attention to the
support expressed by China’s people for their government. In recent surveys
it seems that between 80 and 95% of Chinese citizens were either
relatively or extremely satisfied with central government. Secondly, he
pointed to the stunning economic success that China has enjoyed over
the last thirty years, enjoying a growth rate of about 10% per year.
And this success has not just caused the rich to get richer: Jacques
could also have pointed to China’s remarkable success in lifting its people out of poverty. Allied
to these claims, Jacques argued that the Chinese have a different
conception of the state to that found in the West: for the Chinese, the
state is viewed in terms of the family. Under this conception of the
state, the leadership stands as the head of the family, intimately
connected to, and entitled to exercise authority over, the people.
Each of these three claims deserves further reflection.
Jacques’ first point, resting on statistics that quantified the
satisfaction of the Chinese people with their state, may demonstrate
rather less than he hopes. In Thinking, Fast and Slow, the
psychologist Daniel Kahneman warns of a trick that our minds tend to
play on us. When faced with a difficult question we are tempted to
unknowingly substitute an easier question, and answer that instead. So,
a question about the importance of preserving an animal species or,
perhaps, the effectiveness of the market in the NHS, is transmuted into a
question about the cuteness of the animal or our how we feel about
people making money from healthcare. Similarly, in presenting this poll
as a test of legitimacy, Jacques has shifted from examining the legitimacy of the government to assessing the perception of the legitimacy of
the state. Just because people believe that a government is entitled
to rule, this thought alone does not make it so. Given the control
China exercises over its media, and the absence of any real opposition
to the government, a general belief in the legitimacy of the government
might not be all that surprising.
Indeed, it is even possible that the questions asked by Jacques’
surveys were directed towards something other than the legitimacy of the
government. The surveys appear to have asked after people’s satisfaction with
the state, or their assessment of the government’s handling of the
economy. This is a very different thing to the entitlement of the
government to rule. It is easy to imagine a person – perhaps a subject
in an imperial territory – admitting that the dominating power was
competent, but still challenging its right to rule. The Romans are
still Romans, no matter how well they govern. On the other hand, a
citizen might regard her government as poor, on the verge of
incompetence, but still endorse its legitimacy. Many Labour Party
supporters would bitterly criticise the Coalition’s policies, but still
recognise that the United Kingdom possesses a legitimate government.
This is not just a semantic quibble. Political scientists
distinguish between two forms of legitimacy: input legitimacy and output
legitimacy. Jacques has focused almost exclusively on output
legitimacy in his talk. Output legitimacy is a function of the
competency of the state. People do, or should, support the state and
comply with its commands because doing so will make their community a
better place to live. Input legitimacy, in contrast, is a function of
the way decisions are made. People do, or should, support the state and
comply with its commands because of the way the government has been
formed and the way the commands have been produced. Ordinarily, some
form of democracy is at the heart of input legitimacy. These two forms
of legitimacy are complementary and interconnected. Perhaps one form of
legitimacy is valueless without at least an element of the other. That
the people of China are satisfied with their government, coupled with
the strong economic success of that country, shows that China has a
plausible case to make in terms of output legitimacy. The lack of input
legitimacy may, though, still throw into question the broader
entitlement of the Chinese government to rule.
Jacques’ third point – about the Chinese conception of the state as a
family – might be an indirect response to this point. In the family,
the authority parents enjoy over their children, especially young
children, rests on their ability to make decisions in the best interests
of their child. Parents’ right to tell their children what to do does
not rest on a vote or even on consent. Perhaps Western preconceptions
of legitimacy cannot be applied in the context of China?
The difficulty with this reply is that China does have democratic
structures in its Constitution. These are just not very effective.
In a valuable recent book, Professor Qianfan Zhang explains the structures and operation of the Chinese Constitution. The Constitution asserts
that China should be governed democratically. It sets out a bottom-up
structure of democratic control. The people elect representatives to
the lowest levels of assembly at town and county levels. These
assemblies then elect deputies to sit in Local People’s Congress that,
in their turn, elect deputies to sit in the Congress at the next level
up. The process continues all the way to the National People’s
Congress, which is the highest representative body. In reality, though,
the Communist Party exercises control over every stage of the process:
the bottom-up approach of the Constitution is, as Zhang explains,
countered by a top-down system of Party control. Party committees,
controlled from the centre, are able to vet candidates standing for
election. In effect, the appointment of representatives at each level
of legislature is subject to the review, or even control, of the Party
committee that sits at a governmental level one stage higher than that
body. The 1982 Constitution calls for a system that starts with the
citizen and works up to the NPC, with each deputy accountable to the
lower body that elected her. The constitution with a small ‘c’, in
contrast, starts with power vested at the top of the Party and then
devolves power down to the regions, with each deputy accountable to the
higher body that selected her.
Jeff King has
written of constitutions as mission statements, as declarations of the
type of polity the state wishes to be. In China’s case there is a sharp
contrast between this declaration and the realities of state power.
China’s government fails to achieve legitimacy even in the terms set by
its own Constitution. This creates a sort of constitutional cognitive
dissonance: a discomfort caused by the gap between peoples’ actions and
the way they think they ought to behave. It is a discomfiture that is
very evident amongst Chinese public law scholars who struggle to connect
the Constitution with the actual rules that structure the state. It is
also evident in the speeches of China’s leaders, whose rhetorical
exhortations sometimes seem remote from the state they have fashioned.
Trying to ground a polity largely or entirely in terms of its
competency is a dangerous business. It may prove successful whilst the
economy is booming, but economic success never lasts forever. And the
stability it brings can be quite shallow. After the defenestration of Bo Xilai tanks
were seen on the streets. If this had occurred in London, people would
have thought it was the start of a parade. In Beijing, people thought it was the beginnings of a coup. Chinese
people’s satisfaction in the conduct of their state may be high, but
their faith in their leaders, and their confidence in the stability of
their country, may be less buoyant.